Eliot's literary criticism, still read and admired, {1} is an extraordinary testimony to one man's determination to present his views on poetry as the unquestionable facts of the age. Yet the essays of a major thinker on poetry, {2} who admired close textural criticism, have generally not received the kind of attention their author advocated, {3} and academics still quote approvingly what they would not (one hopes) tolerate in their students' essays. T.S. Eliot was an effective advocate of Modernism, even a brilliant one, but there is often more of the debater's skill than reasoned argument. This was obvious to contemporaries, and should be obvious now, but the essays can still be treated as articles of faith, self-evident and beyond assessment, rather than a source of continuing problems in serious poetry. Supporters leap to arms in defending the indefensible, as discussion of Eliot's very modest anti-Semitism illustrates. {4} Here I look at three key articles, suggesting firstly that Eliot's arguments merit detailed examination and, secondly, that misunderstandings arise through Eliot's expositions, which are rather muddled. Put less charitably, the accusation is that obscurities are of Eliot's own making, and paper over what he would have known were weaknesses and over-simplications. None of what follows makes for easy reading, but I hope visitors will persevere because the issues remain important.
The
1920 Tradition and the Individual Talent {5} was the most influential
of Eliot's essays and makes two claims. First is that poets belong to a
tradition, which supports them and which they modify, allowing past
literature to be seen in a modified light. Second is that poetry is not
an expression of feelings but an escape from feelings: poets are a
catalyst allowing new elements to be combined though they themselves
remain unaltered. The last is the most contentious, and not well expressed in
the essay, but, perhaps because Eliot remains one of the great founders
of Modernism, a protective commentary has grown up to explain what its
author really meant.
Hennekam, {6} for example, believes Eliot is arguing that a poem has
four components: the poet's knowledge of literary tradition and
contemporary literature, his knowledge of structural and genre detail,
his own personality, emotions and circumstances, and his creative
ability. The Wikipedia entry explains that 'What lends greatness to a
work of art are not the feelings and emotions themselves, but the
nature of the artistic process by which they are synthesised.' {7} The
World Heritage Encyclopedia notes 'This fidelity to tradition, however,
does not require the great poet to forfeit novelty in an act of
surrender to repetition. Rather, Eliot has a much more dynamic and
progressive conception of the poetic process: Novelty is possible only
through tapping into tradition. When a poet engages in the creation of
new work, he realises an aesthetic "ideal order," as it has been
established by the literary tradition that has come before him. As
such, the act of artistic creation does not take place in a vacuum. The
introduction of a new work alters the cohesion of this existing order,
and causes a readjustment of the old to accommodate the new. The
inclusion of the new work alters the way in which the past is seen,
elements of the past that are noted and realised. In Eliot's own words:
"What happens when a new work of art is created is something that
happens simultaneously to all the works of art that preceded it." Eliot
refers to this organic tradition, this developing canon, as the "mind
of Europe." The private mind is subsumed by this more massive one.' {8}
The Poetry Foundation's introduction to the essay presents the matter
more fairly, adding that 'But Eliot's belief that critical study should
be "diverted" from the poet to the poetry shaped the study of poetry
for half a century, and while "Tradition and the Individual Talent" has
had many detractors, especially those who question Eliot's insistence
on canonical works as standards of greatness, it is difficult to
overemphasize the essay's influence. It has shaped generations of
poets, critics and theorists and is a key text in modern literary
criticism. ' {9}
Because the essay is short and available from many sources, readers can
readily make up their own minds, but, as I see it, the difficulties
rise from
three tendencies. First, the key terms are not spelt out sufficiently,
and indeed are often used interchangeably. Second, the claims
themselves are by no means convincing or novel when seen against the
general views of aesthetics.
{10} Third, Eliot's breadth of knowledge is presented as a given,
automatically assumed. I will try to tease out these elements from what
is a closely written and sometimes baffling document.
The essay opens with an exploration of tradition, where matters are
overstated in a combative style: 'You can hardly make the word
agreeable to English ears without this comfortable reference to the
reassuring science of archaeology. . . criticism is as inevitable as
breathing . . .' The argument is quite clear, however: tradition is
modified by new works of art. Then we have a tenet of Modernism
smuggled in: 'To conform merely would be for the new work not really to
conform at all; it would not be new, and would therefore not be a work
of art.' The implication here is art requires novelty, and, by
extension, Eliot's new type of poetry. What is left out of account is
what constitutes art, and the nature and extent of novelty possible.
Rather than give examples — which are not hard to find, incidentally —
Eliot then diverts us into a side consideration, drawing the obvious
conclusions: what the contemporary artist models himself upon: the
indiscriminate whole, adolescent enthusiasms, or a preferred period.
Eliot then returns to the main consideration, dismissing the danger
that knowledge or pedantry will deaden the poet's art. He ends this
first half of the essay with 'What is to be insisted upon is that the
poet must develop or procure the consciousness of the past and that he
should continue to develop this consciousness throughout his career.'
Taken
at face value, the argument is not unreasonable but remains rather
theoretical, outlining what Eliot and kindred poets were attempting
rather than what earlier poets had in fact done. Poets are only one
influence, incidentally, as literary critics can have important
insights
(e.g. I. A. Richards and F.R. Leavis) without being practitioners of
the art
they study.
Now we come to the most difficult section, which Eliot introduces with
'The progress of an artist is a continual self-sacrifice, a continual
extinction of personality' by which he did not mean any radical
theory view that texts write themselves. His focus was 'personality'
and that word immediately raises
difficulties because personality is generally seen as
inherent quality persisting in an individual, and not therefore
something that should or could be extinguished. Nonetheless, Eliot
continues with the important statement: 'the mind of the mature poet
differs from that of the immature one not precisely in any valuation of
"personality," not being necessarily more interesting, or having "more
to say," but rather by being a more finely perfected medium in which
special, or very varied, feelings are at liberty to enter into new
combinations'
That
ability to catalyze combinations Eliot illustrates with platinum's
ability to create sulphur trioxide from oxygen and sulphur dioxide. The
mind', he says, 'of the mature poet differs from that of the immature
one not precisely in any valuation of "personality," not being
necessarily more interesting, or having "more to say," but rather by
being a more finely perfected medium in which special, or very varied,
feelings are at liberty to enter into new combinations.' The catalysis
involves elements of two kinds: ' the elements which enter the presence
of the transforming catalyst, are of two kinds: emotions and feelings.'
But what are these two kinds? Does emotion refer to the reader's
response and feeling to the poet's originating sensation, which is
probably the more everyday distinction? Possibly, because Eliot goes on
to say: 'The effect of a work of art upon the person who enjoys it is
an experience different in kind from any experience not of art. It may
be formed out of one emotion, or may be a combination of several; and
various feelings, inhering for the writer in particular words or
phrases or images, may be added to compose the final result.' But then
probably not because Eliot adds: 'Or great poetry may be made without
the direct use of any emotion whatever: composed out of feelings
solely.' Poetry that evoked no emotion from the reader would be
artistically dead, and we must suppose that emotions and feelings both
belong to the poet. But perhaps emotion refers to the overall tone of a
poem, and feelings to the individual characters portrayed, the
protagonists of a play or the implied author of a lyric? But again
probably not. Referring to Canto XV of the Divine Comedy, Eliot
observes: 'The last quatrain gives an image, a feeling attaching to an
image, which "came," which did not develop simply out of what precedes,
but which was probably in suspension in the poet's mind until the
proper combination arrived for it to add itself to. The poet's mind is
in fact a receptacle for seizing and storing up numberless feelings,
phrases, images, which remain there until all the particles which can
unite to form a new compound are present together.' Eliot then gives a
few examples from literature, ending with Keats' nightingale ode.
We are still in the dark over distinctions between personality, emotion
and feelings, however, and remain so in the next paragraph where Eliot
quotes a Middleton passage. This balance of light and dark emotions,
attraction to beauty and repulsion from ugliness is the 'the structural
emotion, provided by the drama.' To this extension of emotion is added:
'It is not in his personal emotions, the emotions provoked by
particular events in his life, that the poet is in any way remarkable
or interesting. . . The business of the poet is not to find new
emotions, but to use the ordinary ones and, in working them up into
poetry, to express feelings which are not in actual emotions at all.
And emotions which he has never experienced will serve his turn as well
as those familiar to him.' (Perhaps these are emotions evoked, but Eliot doesn't say.)
Notwithstanding
Eliot's earlier insistence on there being two kinds of things under
discussion, we have to suppose that feelings, emotions and personality
are all interchangeable entities, though there is now the possibility
that new emotions are created solely by the work of art.
Eliot then attacks the Romantic definition of poetry: 'Consequently, we
must believe that "emotion recollected in tranquillity" is an inexact
formula.' Recollections and tranquility are then explored a little and
we come to the end of the second section of the essay with the famous:
'Poetry is not a turning loose of emotion, but an escape from emotion;
it is not the expression of personality, but an escape from
personality. Naturally, poets still have feelings, possibly stronger
than others: 'But, of course, only those who have personality and
emotions know what it means to want to escape from these things.'
The third section is worth quoting in near totality because it
summarizes the argument and adds a third term: significant emotion. 'To
divert interest from the poet to the poetry is a laudable aim: for it
would conduce to a juster estimation of actual poetry, good and bad.
There are many people who appreciate the expression of sincere emotion
in verse, and there is a smaller number of people who can appreciate
technical excellence. But very few know when there is an expression of
significant emotion, emotion which has its life in the poem and not in
the history of the poet. The emotion of art is impersonal. And the poet
cannot reach this impersonality without surrendering himself wholly to
the work to be done. And he is not likely to know what is to be done
unless he lives in what is not merely the present, but the present
moment of the past, unless he is conscious, not of what is dead, but of
what is already living.'
Is this convincing when Eliot erects an absolute barrier between what
the poem expresses and what the poet is feeling? 'In the Agamemnon, the
artistic emotion approximates to the emotion of an actual spectator; in
Othello to the emotion of the protagonist himself. But the difference
between art and the event is always absolute;' The crux of the matter
is this: if the poet is not expressing emotions /feelings /personality in
writing his poem, or is simply denying them, then it is equally impossible
for him to escape
from feelings etc. through writing poetry. Poetry becomes simply a
diversion, a prestigious one no doubt, but no more salutary than taking
up gardening or joining a bridge-playing circle. The argument, as Eliot
phrases it, falls to the ground.
Repeating matters to be clear, Eliot's argument is this:
The poet's task is to engender emotions specific to the
poem he is writing. Those emotions are created by combining
disparate elements — events, thoughts, strands of previous traditions,
etc. in a particularly sensitive and thoughtful way, an undertaking
that requires personal gifts, intelligence and wide reading. That is
not a controversial view. But Eliot goes further by entirely separating
what the poet feels from the feeling the particular poem evokes, the
poet's personal feelings from the emotions specific to the poem. The
two are not the same. Writing a poem is an impersonal business. But the
trouble then is that if the poet is not expressing his feelings, and cannot be, then the writing of the poem has no connection whatever with personal feelings, and therefore can't in any way be an escape from feelings. Or anything involving personal feelings, not even an evasion or denial of feelings. The two inhabit separate universes, and each is immaterial to the other.
For this misfortune, Eliot has only himself to blame, the
over-cleverness of his attacking and tangled way of writing, which he
had every opportunity to rectify when the essays were republished in
book form. But there
is a further problem. Poet often do
put of lot of themselves into their work, and are commonly seen working
a limited number of themes repeatedly, from youth to maturity. We may
not want to designate the themes as feelings, emotions or
personalities, or suppose they exist independent of their literary
work, but an emotional colouring is nonetheless present. The themes
come from deep inside the psyche, individual and/or communal, and one
can't imagine Eliot writing something like Fern Hill,
for example. Eliot can therefore be as impersonal and tight-lipped as
he wishes, surely so, but should not be basing theories of poetry on
what are only personal preferences.
If, however — which is why I have repeatedly searched for distinctions
between Eliot's terms — emotion were the reader's response, feelings
the originating emotion and personality an inherent part of a poet's
character, then this impasse could be avoided. In Bredon Hill, for
example, we could note the sorrow evoked in the reader as emotion,
Housman's feelings as transferred, since he was not heterosexual, and
pessimism as Housman's inherent personality.
In fact there are better ways of dealing with Eliot's thesis, but I
will delay discussion until we get to the third essay discussed here: Hamlet and his Problems.
Similar
difficulties appear in the 1917 essay Reflections on Vers Libre, {12}
where Eliot is arguing for prosodic freedom. Once again, Eliot is
proselytizing for his brand of poetry, and the examples — 'Both of them
I quote because of their beauty' — are by T.E. Hulme and Ezra Pound.
The first starts with hyperbaton and a trivializing excess of
alliteration: 'Once in a finesse of fiddles found I ecstasy'. The
second ends with the problematic line 'A broken bundle of mirrors . .
', where the poet who remarked that the writer must have its wits about
him at all times seems not to have realized that medieval ladies were
not beset by bundles of mirrors, broken or otherwise. In fact, the fragile glass and
silver-backed mirror appears only in Renaissance Florence. Small points. But
what is important is the whole tenor of the argument, which inserts one
half truth into another. 'What sort of a line that would not scan at
all I cannot say' remarks Eliot, knowing perfectly well that scansion,
how we represent the pattern of stress, half-stress and no stress
(I am simplifying) is not equivalent to a line 'scanning', where
we expect some regularity of pattern. That 'some' can be very general,
of course, something only vaguely sensed behind the written line, as
Eliot himself notes: 'the ghost of some simple meter should lurk behind
the arras in even the "freest" verse'.
But why be so
categorical? (In fact, as later poets were to demonstrate, it is also
possible to write lines in prose, which do not scan in any generally
accepted way.) Then we have one of those glancing blows that Eliot was
so fond of delivering, here directed at Swinburne: ''Swinburne mastered
his technique, which is a great deal, but he did not master it to the
extent of being able to take liberties with it, which is everything.'
Is it? And no liberties in 'Seals, whales, storks, elephants, bears,
monkeys, geese, / And more, can all be made by young and old. /
Menageries on your own mantelpiece!' (Menageries {12}). Again, the
example is unimportant, except to emphasize the unwisdom of giving
hostages to fortune in these unneeded sallies.
Then we pass to the early seventeenth century, to John Webster, 'who
was in some ways a more cunning technician than Shakespeare.' In The
White Devil, Webster forgoes regularity in the moments of highest
intensity, the irregularity being further enhanced by the use of short
lines and the breaking up of lines in dialogue.' Perhaps so, though
whether Webster is the more cunning technician than Shakespeare is
debatable. Shakespeare can also take great liberties with key lines,
and his verse becomes more 'intuitive' in the later plays. {13} But
license is not a law of nature. Pope maintains a variety in regularity,
and some great poets, Racine and Pushkin, for example, write remarkably
regular lines throughout. Nor are the examples Eliot that provides
those of intense emotion. The argument so far is not
over-convincing, I'd suggest, and is certainly not helped by the
erudition, or seeming erudition, which only complicates matters.
A comparison of Edgar Lee Masters (Spoon River Anthology) with George
Crabbe follows, which finds Crabbe's verse is 'the more intense of the
two; he is keen, direct and unsparing. . . Mr. Masters requires a more
rigid verse form. . .' Indeed he does. Much seems to be prose, or close
to it, which is hazardous to Eliot's case that all poetry can be
scanned:
Have you seen walking through the village
A man with downcast eyes and haggard face?
That is my husband who, by secret cruelty
Never to be told, robbed me of my youth and my beauty; {14}
Next appears the gnomic 'So much for meter. There is no escape from
meter; there is only mastery.' But since metre is a systematic
regularity in rhythm, which the Masters example does not display, it is
difficult to know what Eliot is arguing. That the verse of the then
popular Spoon River Anthology lacks mastery? Possibly, but then it
would help to say so. And to find some other poet than Crabbe with
which to compare Masters since centuries of sensibility separate the
two.
Passing on, we come to two sections of verse, one by H.D. and the other
by Thomas Arnold, where to me, a century after Eliot's claiming 'What
neither Blake nor Arnold could do alone is being done in our time',
Arnold's seems the more 'modern'. Again, this is unfortunate: Eliot is
summoning as evidence what seems to undermine his argument that
there is no vers libre as such, only a better understanding of verse
generally, which his and contemporary poetry exemplified.
The last two paragraphs deal with rhymeless verse, arguing that the
removal of rhyme throws other verse devices into higher relief. Few
would object to the thesis but, unfortunately, once again, we have the
Eliot love of paradox. 'Rhyme removed, ' he declares, 'the poet is at
once held up to the standards of prose.' Prose, with its strong
emphasis on making discursive sense? Eliot continues, 'Rhyme removed,
much ethereal music leaps up from the word, which has hitherto chirped
unnoticed in the expanse of prose.' Leaps up? Chirps? Perhaps this is
humour, or the master is playing with his readers. But probably not:
the essay ends soberly with 'we conclude that the division between
Conservative Verse and vers libre does not exist, for there is only
good verse, bad verse, and chaos.'
By now the conscientious reader should be feeling uneasy. Important
distinctions have been thrown away, and only Eliot and his like-minded
poets are to deliberate on aesthetics, which, on the examples given,
and in the absence of clear rules, or any rules at all, seems a very
dubious proposition.
With Hamlet and his Problems {15} (collected in The Sacred Wood, 1921)
Eliot is even more dismissive of earlier critics, including Goethe,
Coleridge and Pater, but allows contemporaries the credit of moving in
the right direction. Hamlet is not solely Shakespeare's creation, but a
reworking of material from Kyd and others. Being cobbled together in
this fashion, the play is also an artistic failure. It has unnecessary
scenes. The verse style is inconsistent. Hamlet's feelings towards his
guilty mother make an impossible theme for drama. Because these
repressed feelings can't be dragged into the light, moreover, the only
avenue left open is the 'objective correlative', defined as: 'in other
words, a set of objects, a situation, a chain of events which shall be
the formula of that particular emotion; such that when the external
facts, which must terminate in sensory experience, are given, the
emotion is immediately evoked'. Other plays, like Macbeth, are more
successful in this regard. 'The artistic "inevitability" lies in this
complete adequacy of the external to the emotion; and this is precisely
what is deficient in Hamlet.' Hamlet has to escape into madness, a ruse
on Shakespeare's part that leaves the unmentionable matter untreated.
More than this, Eliot does not say, which has allowed later writers to
expand the term into a general symbolic device. {16-19} Contemporaries
were less convinced, however, as my page on Ezra Pound indicates {20}
and it seems unwise to make speculations as to what Shakespeare could
and could not do into support for the concept of objective correlate.
Not all critics see Hamlet as an artistic failure, moreover.
But we don't need to blunder into these theoretical tangles. One way of
dealing with emotional expression is to understand how poets work.
Writing is commonly a two-way process, where the poet is continually switching
between creator and audience, from 'does this really express how I felt
or could now feel?' to 'will this work for the reader?' A poem is a
dialogue between what the poet has so far written, and what the piece
suggests could be its eventual achievement. Art is not simply skill in
expressing emotion, therefore, but also a skill in evoking
the appropriate emotion in the reader. Into that appropriate emotion come many
other matters as well: traditions, readers' expectations, genres,
rhetorical devices, imagery and metaphor, scansion, aesthetic
detachment and shaping, etc. The successful poem is a fusion of these
elements, where the whole is self-referencing and therefore larger than the sum of its ingredients.
{10}
Eliot
surely knew this. His training was in philosophy, moreover, which will
have covered some aspects of aesthetics. Why set off such wild goose
chases after meaning unless it was not clear exposition Eliot was
after, but status, for himself and the poetry he espoused? He was
extraordinarily productive under very difficult circumstances — money
troubles, failing marriage, long hours as a bank official — and the
hundred odd essays published between 1916 and 1923 {21} point not only
to someone unusually ambitious but possibly also tormented and self-driven.
There are many successful poems in Prufrock, but their ambiance is
distinctly strange, forbidding even. In short, was not Eliot a deeply
troubled man, to which later events only testify: The Waste Land, The Hollow Men, religious conversion, personal papers kept out of
circulation by his second wife?
Why, moreover, did contemporary poets and the reading public submit to this air of invincible authority? Were they cowed by the
erudition? Did they seek publication in the avant garde world over
which Eliot presided? Or did they simply not want to give up the time
to matters that seemed tangential to poetry?
Eliot's criticism was therefore both salutary and unfortunate. He made
criticism the subject of serious study and more than genial rambles in
personal taste. But he also made the subject unnecessarily difficult
and partisan. To personal preferences were added personal neuroses,
though Eliot was not alone in the despair widespread after the
horrific
slaughter of WWI. Scrutiny and other journals provided The New
Criticism with useful technical audits of literature, valuable to
writers as to general readers, but the theoretical aspects once more
gained the upper hand in the critical theory that followed WWII.
Matters had once been fairly straightforward. Prose aimed for
discursive clarity, and poetry for the infinite shades of meaning,
emotive force, tone and implication that are possible, perhaps
unavoidable, in language used in its wider remit. Now the positioning
was reversed, and critical evaluation became far more astute and
interesting than the poetry it purported to explain, for all that both,
unfortunately, could be wondrously wrong-headed. Much of today's radical literary theory {22} seems to have begun with Eliot's
over-clever essays.
With hindsight, looking back the forty years since I first read these
essays, I even more suspect the obsfucation was deliberate. Tradition is
rightly stressed by Eliot, but the
larger point — to what extent, why and how previous poetry can be
incorporated into contemporary poetry — is not asked. Because his own
work evaded the need for old words to be given new settings? The Wasteland
does not recreate language — i.e. rehabilitate, re-envison and deepen
the usage of words expected of poetry — so much as employ collages of
quotation and everyday prose. That prose orientation has become
mainstream — in the subject matter of poetry, its techniques and
preoccupations. Topics of elevated and universal interest have been
relegated to amateur verse, and serious poetry now deals with the
quotidian of life. Metered verse became free verse, and is often now
prose in all but name. The philosophy of language and meaning, subjects
taxing even in thoughtful prose, have become woven into the fabric of
modern poetry, often without a proper grasp of the principles. I doubt if Eliot
intended this. The essays had a proselytising role, but it seems hard to escape the conclusion that the
gaps, opacities and suppressions in Eliot's own argumentive style set modern poetry on an unfortunate course.
References can now be found in a free pdf compilation of Ocaso Press's modern poets.